Art and Interpretation

picture of man looking at art objectsInterpretation in art refers to the attribution of meaning to a piece of work. A bespeak on which people often disagree is whether the creative person'due south or author'due south intention is relevant to the interpretation of the work. In the Anglo-American analytic philosophy of art, views about interpretation co-operative into two major camps: intentionalism and anti-intentionalism, with an initial focus on ane art, namely literature.

The anti-intentionalist maintains that a work'due south meaning is entirely determined past linguistic and literary conventions, thereby rejecting the relevance of the author'southward intention. The underlying assumption of this position is that a work enjoys autonomy with respect to meaning and other aesthetically relevant backdrop. Extra-textual factors, such as the writer's intention, are neither necessary nor sufficient for meaning determination. This early position in the analytic tradition is often called conventionalism because of its stiff emphasis on convention. Anti-intentionalism gradually went out of favor at the terminate of the 20th century, but information technology has seen a revival in the so-chosen value-maximizing theory, which recommends that the interpreter seek value-maximizing interpretations constrained by convention and, according to a dissimilar version of the theory, by the relevant contextual factors at the time of the work'southward production.

Past contrast, the initial brand of intentionalism—actual intentionalism—holds that interpreters should concern themselves with the author's intention, for a work's pregnant is affected by such intention. There are at least three versions of actual intentionalism. The absolute version identifies a piece of work'due south meaning fully with the author'south intention, therefore allowing that an author can intend her work to mean whatsoever she wants it to mean. The extreme version acknowledges that the possible meanings a work can sustain have to be constrained past convention. According to this version, the writer's intention picks the correct pregnant of the work as long as it fits one of the possible meanings; otherwise, the piece of work ends up being meaningless. The moderate version claims that when the author'southward intention does not match any of the possible meanings, significant is stock-still instead by convention and perhaps also context.

A second brand of intentionalism, which finds a middle course between bodily intentionalism and anti-intentionalism, is hypothetical intentionalism. According to this position, a work's meaning is the advisable audience'southward best hypothesis nearly the writer's intention based on publicly bachelor information almost the author and her work at the fourth dimension of the piece's production. A variation on this position attributes the intention to a hypothetical author who is postulated by the interpreter and who is constituted by work features. Such authors are sometimes said to be fictional considering they, existence purely conceptual, differ decisively from flesh-and-blood authors.

This article elaborates on these theories of interpretation and considers their notable objections. The argue about estimation covers other fine art forms in addition to literature. The theories of interpretation are also extended beyond many of the arts. This broad outlook is assumed throughout the article, although nix said is afflicted fifty-fifty if a narrow focus on literature is adopted.

Table of Contents

  1. Fundamental Concepts: Intention, Significant, and Interpretation
  2. Anti-Intentionalism
    1. The Intentional Fallacy
    2. Beardsley's Speech Human activity Theory of Literature
    3. Notable Objections and Replies
  3. Value-Maximizing Theory
    1. Overview
    2. Notable Objections and Replies
  4. Actual Intentionalism
    1. Absolute Version
    2. Farthermost Version
    3. Moderate Version
    4. Objections to Bodily Intentionalism
  5. Hypothetical Intentionalism
    1. Overview
    2. Notable Objections and Replies
  6. Hypothetical Intentionalism and the Hypothetical Artist
    1. Overview
    2. Notable Objections and Replies
  7. Decision
  8. References and Further Reading

1. Key Concepts: Intention, Meaning, and Interpretation

It is mutual for united states to enquire questions about works of art due to puzzlement or curiosity. Sometimes we do not understand the bespeak of the work. What is the point of, for instance, Metamorphosis by Kafka or Duchamp's Fountain? Sometimes there is ambiguity in a work and we want information technology resolved. For instance, is the final sequence of Christopher Nolan'due south film Inception reality or some other dream? Or exercise ghosts really exist in Henry James's The Turn of the Screw? Sometimes we brand hypotheses virtually details in a piece of work. For instance, does the woman in white in Raphael's The School of Athens represent Hypatia? Is the conch in William Golding'south Lord of the Flies a symbol for culture and democracy?

What these questions have in common is that all of them seek afterwards things that get beyond what the work literally presents or says. They are all concerned with the implicit contents of the piece of work or, for simplicity, with the meanings of a work. A distinction tin be drawn betwixt two kinds of pregnant in terms of scope. Meaning can be global in the sense that it concerns the work's theme, thesis, or signal. For example, an audience first encountering Duchamp's Fountain would want to know Duchamp'southward point in producing this readymade or, put otherwise, what the work equally a whole is made to convey. The same goes for Kafka'south Metamorphosis, which contains so baroque a plot as to brand the reader wonder what the story is all near. Meaning tin can besides be local insofar as it is almost what a function of a work conveys. Inquiries into the meaning of a particular sequence in Christopher Nolan's picture, the woman in Raphael'south fresco, or the conch in William Golding's Lord of the Flies are directed at simply function of the work.

We are said to exist interpreting when trying to find out answers to questions about the significant of a work. In other words, estimation is the attempt to attribute piece of work-meaning. Here "aspect" tin mean "recover," which is retrieving something already existing in a work; or information technology tin more weakly mean "impose," which entails ascribing a meaning to a work without ontologically creating anything. Many of the major positions in the debate endorse either the impositional view or the retrieval view.

When an interpretative question arises, a frequent way to deal with it is to resort to the creator'southward intention. We may inquire the creative person to reveal her intention if such an opportunity is available; nosotros may as well cheque what she says about her work in an interview or autobiography. If we have access to her personal documents such as diaries or messages, they too volition become our interpretative resources. These are all evidence of the artist's intention. When the bear witness is compelling, nosotros accept adept reason to believe it reveals the artist'south intention.

Certainly, there are cases in which external show of the artist's intention is absent, including when the work is anonymous. This poses no difficulty for philosophers who view entreatment to artistic intention as crucial, for they accept that internal evidence—the work itself—is the best evidence of the artist's intention. Near of the fourth dimension, close attention to details of the work will lead u.s.a. to what the artist intended the work to mean.

But what is intention exactly? Intention is a kind of mental land usually characterized as a blueprint or plan in the artist's mind to exist realized in her artistic creation. This crude view of intention is sometimes refined into the reductive analysis one volition find in a contemporaneous textbook of philosophy of listen: intention is constituted by belief and want. Some bodily intentionalists explain the nature of intention from a Wittgensteinian perspective: authorial intention is viewed as the purposive structure of the work that tin be discerned by close inspection. This view challenges the supposition that intentions are always individual and logically independent of the work they crusade, which is often interpreted as a position held by anti-intentionalists.

A 2005 proposal holds that intentions are executive attitudes toward plans (Livingston). These attitudes are firm but defeasible commitments to interim on them. Contra the reductive assay of intention, this view holds that intentions are distinct and real mental states that serve a range of functions irreducible to other mental states.

Clarifying each of these bones terms (significant, estimation, and intention) requires an essay-length treatment that cannot exist done hither. For electric current purposes, information technology suffices to introduce the aforesaid views and proposals unremarkably assumed. Bear in listen that for the almost office the debate over art estimation gain without consensus on how to define these terms, and clarifications announced only when necessary.

ii. Anti-Intentionalism

Anti-intentionalism is considered the first theory of interpretation to emerge in the analytic tradition. It is commonly seen as affiliated with the New Criticism movement that was prevalent in the heart of the twentieth century. The position was initially a reaction against biographical criticism, the main idea of which is that the interpreter, to grasp the significant of a work, needs to report the life of the writer because the work is seen as reflecting the writer's mental world. This approach led to people because the author's biographical information rather than her piece of work. Literary criticism became criticism of biography, not criticism of literary works. Confronting this trend, literary critic William K. Wimsatt and philosopher Monroe C. Beardsley coauthored a seminal newspaper "The Intentional Fallacy" in 1946, marking the starting point of the intention debate. Beardsley subsequently extended his anti-intentionalist stance across the arts in his monumental volume Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism ([1958] 1981a).

a. The Intentional Fallacy

The principal idea of the intentional fallacy is that appeal to the creative person'due south intention exterior the piece of work is fallacious, because the work itself is the verdict of what meaning it bears. This contention is based on the anti-intentionalist's ontological supposition about works of art.

This underlying assumption is that a work of art enjoys autonomy with respect to pregnant and other aesthetically relevant properties. As Beardsley'south Principle of Autonomy shows, critical statements volition in the end need to be tested confronting the work itself, not against factors outside information technology. To give Beardsley's example, whether a statue symbolizes man destiny depends not on what its maker says but on our being able to make out that theme from the statue on the basis of our knowledge of artistic conventions: if the statue shows a man confined to a muzzle, we may well conclude that the statue indeed symbolizes homo destiny, for past convention the prototype of confinement fits that alleged theme. The anti-intentionalist principle hence follows: the interpreter should focus on what she tin can notice in the work itself—the internal prove—rather than on external evidence, such as the artist's biography, to reveal her intentions.

Anti-intentionalism is sometimes called conventionalism because information technology sees convention as necessary and sufficient in determining piece of work-meaning. On this view, the creative person's intention at all-time underdetermines meaning even when operating successfully. This can exist seen from the famous statement offered by Wimsatt and Beardsley: either the artist's intention is successfully realized in the piece of work, or it fails; if the intention is successfully realized in the work, appeal to external bear witness of the artist's intention is not necessary (nosotros can detect the intention from the work); if information technology fails, such appeal becomes insufficient (the intention turns out to be extraneous to the work). The conclusion is that an entreatment to external prove of the creative person'south intention is either unnecessary or insufficient. As the 2d premise of the argument shows, the artist'south intention is bereft in determining meaning for the reason that convention lonely can do the flim-flam. As a consequence, the overall argument entails the irrelevance of external evidence of the artist's intention. To recall of such evidence as relevant commits the intentional fallacy.

In that location is a second way to formulate the intentional fallacy. Since the artist does not e'er successfully realize her intention, the inference is invalid from the premise that the artist intended her work to mean p to the conclusion that the piece of work in question does mean p. Therefore, the term "intentional fallacy" has two layers of meaning: normatively, it refers to the questionable principle of interpretation that external testify of intent should be appealed to; ontologically, it refers to the fallacious inference from probable intention to work-meaning.

b. Beardsley's Speech Act Theory of Literature

Beardsley at a later signal develops an ontology of literature in favor of anti-intentionalism (1981b, 1982). Reviving Plato's imitation theory of art, Beardsley claims that fictional works are essentially imitations of illocutionary acts. Briefly put, illocutionary acts are performed past utterances in particular contexts. For example, when a detective, convinced that someone is the killer, points his finger at that person and utters the judgement "you did it," the detective is performing the illocutionary deed of accusing someone. What illocutionary act is being performed is traditionally construed as jointly determined by the speaker's intention to perform that human action, the words uttered, and the relevant conditions in that detail context. Other examples of illocutionary acts include asserting, alarm, punitive, request, and the like.

Literary works tin be seen equally utterances; that is, texts used in a particular context to perform dissimilar illocutionary acts by authors. However, Beardsley claims that in the case of fictional works in detail, the purported illocutionary force will always be removed so equally to brand the utterance an faux of that illocutionary act. When an attempted act is insufficiently performed, it ends upwardly being represented or imitated. For example, if I say "please pass me the salt" in my dining room when no one except me is there, I end up representing (imitating) the illocutionary act of requesting because there is no uptake from the intended audience. Since the illocutionary act in this case is only imitated, it qualifies every bit a fictional human activity. This is why Beardsley sees fiction as representation.

Consider the uptake condition in the case of fictional works. Such works are non addressed to the audition as a talk is: there is no concrete context in which the audience can be readily identified. The uttered text hence loses its illocutionary force and ends up being a representation. Bated from this "address without admission," another obtaining condition for a fictional illocutionary act is the beingness of non-referring names and descriptions in a fictional work. If an author writes a poem in which she greets the dandy detective Sherlock Holmes, this greeting will never obtain, because the proper name Sherlock Holmes does not refer to any existing person in the world. The greeting will only end upward beingness a representation or a fictional illocution. By parity of reasoning, fictional works end upward being representations of illocutionary acts in that they always incorporate names or descriptions involving events that never take place.

Now nosotros must ask: by what criterion practice we make up one's mind what illocutionary act is represented? It cannot be the speaker or writer's intention, because even if a speaker intends to stand for a item illocutionary deed, she might stop up representing another. Since the possibility of failed intention e'er exists, intention would not exist an appropriate benchmark. Convention is over again invoked to determine the correct illocutionary deed being represented. It is true that any practice of representing is intentional at the commencement in the sense that what is represented is determined past the representer'southward intention. Nevertheless, in one case the connection between a symbol and what it is used to correspond is established, intention is said to be detached from that connection, and deciding the content of a representation becomes a sheer matter of convention.

Since a fictional piece of work is essentially a representation of an insufficiently performed illocutionary act, determining what it represents does not require us to go beyond that incomplete operation, only every bit determining what a mime is imitating does not require the audition to consider anything outside her performance, such equally her intention. What the mime is imitating is completely determined by how we conventionally construe the deed being performed. In a similar fashion, when because what illocutionary deed is represented by a fictional piece of work, the interpreter should rely on internal evidence rather than on external testify of authorial intent to construct the illocutionary human activity being represented. If, based on internal data, a story reads similar a castigation of state of war, it is suitably seen as a representation of that illocutionary human activity. The conclusion is that the writer's intention plays no role in fixing the content of a fictional work.

Lastly, it is worth mentioning that Beardsley's attitude toward nonfictional works is ambivalent. Patently, his speech human activity argument applies to fictional works just, and he accepts that nonfictional works can be genuine illocutions. This category of works tends to have a more identifiable audience, who is hence non addressed without access. With illocutions, Beardsley continues to contend for an anti-intentionalist view of pregnant according to which the utterer's intention does not determine meaning. But his accepting nonfictional works every bit illocutions opens the door to considerations of external or contextual factors that go against his before stance, which is globally anti-intentionalist.

c. Notable Objections and Replies

One immediate concern with anti-intentionalism is whether convention lonely can point to a unmarried pregnant (Hirsch, 1967). The common reason why people debate well-nigh estimation is precisely that the work itself does not offering sufficient evidence to disambiguate significant. Very oft a work can sustain multiple meanings and the problem of option prompts some people to appeal to the artist's intention. It does not seem plausible to say that one tin assign only a unmarried meaning to works similar Ulysses or Picasso's abstract paintings if one concentrates solely on internal prove. To this objection, Beardsley (1970) insists that, in nearly cases, appeal to the coherence of the work can somewhen leave us with a single correct interpretation.

A 2d serious objection to anti-intentionalism is the case of irony (Hirsch, 1976, pp. 24–5). Information technology seems reasonable to say that whether a work is ironic depends on if its creator intended it to be so. For case, based on internal evidence, many people took Daniel Defoe'due south pamphlet The Shortest Way with the Dissenters to be genuinely against the Dissenters upon its publication. However, the simply ground for saying that the pamphlet is ironic seems to be Defoe'southward intention. If irony is a crucial component of the piece of work, ignoring it would fail to respect the work's identity. It follows that irony cannot be grounded in internal evidence lonely. Beardsley's answer (1982, pp. 203–vii) is that irony must offer the possibility of understanding. If the artist cannot imagine anyone taking it ironically, there would be no reason to believe the work to be ironic.

Even so, the trouble of irony is only part of a bigger concern that challenges the irrelevance of external factors to interpretation. Many factors nowadays at the fourth dimension of the work's creation seem to play a key function in shaping a work's identity and content. Missing out on these factors would lead us to misidentifying the piece of work (and hence to misinterpreting it).

For example, a work will non exist seen equally revolutionary unless the interpreter knows something about the contemporaneous artistic tradition: ignoring the work's innovation amounts to accepting that the work can lose its revolutionary character while remaining self-identical. If we see this graphic symbol equally identity-relevant, we should then take it into consideration in our interpretation. The same line of thinking goes for other identity-conferring contextual factors, such equally the social-historical conditions and the relations the work bears to contemporaneous or prior works. The present view is thus called ontological contextualism to foreground the ontological claim that the identity and content of a work of art are in part determined by the relations information technology bears to its context of product.

Contextualism leads to an important distinction between work and text in the case of literature. In a nutshell: a text is non context-dependent but a work is. The anti-intentionalist opinion thus leads the interpreter to consider texts rather than works because it rejects considerations of external or contextual factors. The same stardom goes for other art forms when we draw a comparison between an artistic product considered in its brute form and in its context of creation. For convenience, the word "work" is used throughout with notes on whether contextualism is taken or not.

As a respond to the contextualist objection, it has been argued (Davies, 2005) that Beardsley'south position allows for contextualism. If this is convincing, the contextualist criticism of anti-intentionalism would not exist conclusive.

3. Value-Maximizing Theory

a. Overview

The value-maximizing theory tin be viewed as being derived from anti-intentionalism. Its core claim is that the chief aim of art interpretation is to offer interpretations that maximize the value of a work. In that location are at to the lowest degree two versions of the maximizing position distinguished by the commitment to contextualism. When the maximizing position is committed to contextualism, the constraint on estimation will exist convention plus context (Davies, 2007); otherwise, the constraint will be convention only, as endorsed by anti-intentionalism (Goldman, 2013).

As indicated, the word "maximize" does not imply monism. That is, the nowadays position does non merits that there can be only a single manner to maximize the value of a work of art. On the opposite, it seems reasonable to assume that in virtually cases the interpreter can envisage several readings to bring out the value of the work. For example, Kafka's Metamorphosis has generated a number of rewarding interpretations, and it is difficult to fence for a single all-time among them. Every bit long every bit an interpretation is revealing or insightful under the relevant interpretative constraints, nosotros may count information technology as value-maximizing. Such being the example, the value-maximizing theory may be relabelled the "value-enhancing" or "value-satisfying" theory.

Given this pluralist flick, the maximizer, different the anti-intentionalist, will need to take the indeterminacy thesis that convention (and context, if she endorses contextualism) lonely does non guarantee the unambiguity of the work. This allows the maximizing position to bypass the challenge posed by said thesis, rendering it a more than flexible position than anti-intentionalism in regard to the number of legitimate interpretations.

Encapsulating the maximizing position in a few words: it holds that the main aim of fine art interpretation is to enhance beholden satisfaction by identifying interpretations that bring out the value of a piece of work within reasonable limits set by convention (and context).

b. Notable Objections and Replies

The actual intentionalist will maintain that figurative features such as irony and allusion must exist analysed intentionalistically. The maximizer with contextualist commitment tin counter this objection past dealing with intentions more than sophisticatedly. If the relevant features are identity conferring, they will be respected and accepted in interpretation. In this instance, any interpretation that ignores the intended characteristic ends up misidentifying the work. Merely if the relevant features are non identity conferring, more room will be left for the interpreter to consider them. The intended characteristic tin can be ignored if information technology does not add to the value of the work. Past dissimilarity, where such a feature is non intended but can be put in the work, the interpreter can still build it into the interpretation if it is value enhancing.

The almost important objection to the maximizing view has it that the present position is in danger of turning a mediocre work into a masterpiece. Ed Wood's film Plan 9 from Outer Space is the most discussed case. Many people consider this work to exist the worst film ever made. However, interpreted from a postmodern perspective as satire—which is presumably a value-enhancing interpretation—would turn it into a classic.

The maximizer with contextualist leanings can respond that the postmodern reading fails to identify the picture show as authored by Wood (Davies, 2007, p, 187). Postmodern views were not bachelor in Wood's time, and so it was incommunicable for the film to be created equally such. Identifying the film as postmodernist amounts to anachronism that disrespects the work's identity. The moral of this case is that the maximizer does not blindly heighten the value of a work. Rather, the work to be interpreted needs to exist contextualized first to ensure that subsequent attributions of aesthetic value are done in low-cal of the true and fair presentation of the work.

iv. Actual Intentionalism

Contra anti-intentionalism, actual intentionalism maintains that the artist's intention is relevant to interpretation. The position comes in at least 3 forms, giving unlike weights to intention. The absolute version claims that work-significant is fully determined past the artist'southward intention; the extreme version claims that the piece of work ends up beingness meaningless when the creative person's intention is incompatible with information technology; and the moderate version claims that either the artist's intention determines meaning or—if this fails—meaning is determined instead by convention (and context, if contextualism is endorsed).

a. Absolute Version

Absolute actual intentionalism claims that a work ways whatever its creator intends it to hateful. Put otherwise, it sees the artist'southward intention equally the necessary and sufficient condition for a work's meaning. This position is oft dubbed Humpty-Dumptyism with reference to the character Humpty-Dumpty in Through the Looking-Glass. This character tries to convince Alice that he can make a discussion mean what he chooses it to mean. This unsettling conclusion is supported by the argument about intentionless meaning: a mark (or a sequence of marks) cannot take meaning unless it is produced past an agent capable of intentional activities; therefore, significant is identical to intention.

It seems plausible to abandon the thought that marks on the sand are a poem in one case we know they were acquired by accident. Only this at all-time proves that intention is the necessary condition for something's being meaningful; it does not prove further that what something means is what the agent intended information technology to hateful. In other words, the argument virtually intentionless meaning does a better job in showing that intention is an indispensable ingredient for meaningfulness than in showing that intention infallibly determines the meaning conveyed.

b. Extreme Version

To avoid Humpty-Dumptyism, the extreme bodily intentionalist rejects the view that the creative person'southward intention infallibly determines work-significant and accepts the indeterminacy thesis that convention solitary does not guarantee a single evident meaning to be found in a work. The farthermost intentionalist claims further that the significant of the work is fixed by the artist's intention if her intention identifies 1 of the possible meanings sustained past the work; otherwise, the work ends up being meaningless (Hirsch, 1967). Ameliorate put, the extreme intentionalist sees intention as the necessary rather than sufficient condition for piece of work-meaning.

Bated from the unsatisfactory result that a work becomes meaningless when the artist'due south intention fails, the present position faces a dilemma when dealing with the case of figurative language (Nathan, in Iseminger (1992)). Take irony for example. The first horn of the dilemma is every bit follows: Constrained by linguistic conventions, the range of possible meanings has to include the negation of the literal meaning in social club for the intended irony to exist effective. But this results in accented intentionalism: every expression would exist ironic as long as the author intends it to be. Merely—this is the second horn—if the range of possible meanings does non include the negation of literal significant, the expression simply becomes meaningless in that in that location is no appropriate meaning possible for the author to concretize. It seems that a broader notion of convention is needed to explain figurative language. Simply if the extreme intentionalist makes that move, her intentionalist position volition be undermined, for the author's intention would exist given a less important role than convention in such cases. Nevertheless, this problem does non ascend when the bodily intentionalist is committed to contextualism, for in that case the contextual factors that make the intended irony possible will be taken into account.

c. Moderate Version

Though there are several different versions of moderate bodily intentionalism, they share the common footing that when the creative person'south intention fails, meaning is fixed instead past convention and context. (Whether all moderate actual intentionalists take context into account is controversial and this commodity volition not dig into this controversy for reasons of infinite.) That is, when the artist'south intention is successful, it determines significant; otherwise, meaning is determined by convention plus context (Carroll, 2001; Stecker, 2003; Livingston, 2005).

As seen, an intention is successful and so long as it identifies one of the possible meanings sustained by the work even if the meaning identified is less plausible than other candidates. But what exactly is the interpreter doing when she identifies that meaning? It is reasonable to say that the interpreter does not demand to ascertain all the possible meanings and encounter if there is a fit. Rather, all she needs to do is to see whether the intended meaning tin can be read in accordance with the piece of work. This is why the moderate intentionalist puts the success condition in terms of compatibility: an intention is successful so long as the intended meaning is uniform with the piece of work. The fact that a certain significant is uniform with the piece of work ways that the work can sustain it as one of its possible meanings.

Unfortunately, the notion of compatibility seems to allow strange cases in which an insignificant intention can decide work-meaning as long as it is not explicitly rejected by the relevant interpretative constraint. For instance, if Agatha Christie reveals that Hercule Poirot is actually a smart Martian in disguise, the moderate intentionalist would need to take information technology because this annunciation of intention can all the same be said to be uniform with the text in the sense that it is not rejected by textual bear witness. To avert this bad consequence, compatibility needs to be qualified.

The moderate intentionalist and then analyses compatibility in terms of the meshing condition, which refers to a sufficient degree of coherence between the content of the intention and the work'southward rhetorical patterns. An intention is uniform with the piece of work in the sense that it meshes well with the work. The Martian case will hence exist ruled out past the meshing status because it does not appoint sufficiently with the narrative even if it is not explicitly rejected by textual testify. The meshing status is a minimal or weak success condition in that information technology does non require the intention to mesh with every textual feature. A sufficient amount will practice, though the moderate intentionalist admits that the line is not always easy to draw. With this weak standard for success, it can happen that the interpreter is not able to discern the intended meaning in the work before she learns of the artist's intention.

There is a 2nd kind of success condition which adopts a stronger standard (Stecker, 2003; Davies, 2007, pp. 170–i). This standard for success states that an intention is successful merely in case the intended meaning, among the possible meanings sustained by the piece of work, is the i nearly probable to secure uptake from a well-backgrounded audition (with contextual noesis and all). For example, if a work of art, within the limits set by convention and context, affords interpretations x, y, and z, and x is more readily discerned than the other two by the appropriate audience, then x is the meaning of the work.

These accounts of the success status respond a notable objection to moderate intentionalism. This objection claims that moderate intentionalism faces an epistemic dilemma (Trivedi, 2001). Consider an epistemic question: how exercise nosotros know whether an intention is successfully realized? Presumably, we figure out work-meaning and the artist'due south intention respectively and independently of each other. And then we compare the two to see if there is a fit. Nonetheless, this movement is redundant: if nosotros can effigy out work-meaning independently of actual intention, why do we demand the latter? And if piece of work-significant cannot exist independently obtained, how can nosotros know it is a example where intentions are successfully realized and not a case where intentions failed? It follows that appeal to successful intention results in back-up or indeterminacy.

The first horn of the dilemma assumes that piece of work-meaning can exist obtained independently of cognition of successful intention, but this is false for moderate intentionalists, for they acknowledge that in many cases the work presents ambiguity that cannot be resolved solely in virtue of internal bear witness. The moderate intentionalist rejects the 2d horn by claiming that they do not determine the success of an intention past comparing independently obtained work-meaning with the artist's intention (Stecker, 2010, pp. 154–5). As already discussed, moderate intentionalists propose different success weather that practice not appeal to the identity between the artist'due south intention and piece of work-meaning. Moderate intentionalists adopting the weak standard hold that success is defined by the degree of meshing; those who adopt the strong standard maintain that success is defined past the audience'due south ability to grasp the intention. Neither requires the interpreter to place a work'southward significant independently of the artist'southward intention.

d. Objections to Actual Intentionalism

The virtually commonly raised objection is the epistemic worry, which asks: is intention knowable? Information technology seems incommunicable for one to really know others' mental states, and the epistemic gap in this respect is thus unbridgeable. Bodily intentionalists tend to dismiss this worry as insignificant and maintain that in many contexts (daily conversation or historical investigations) nosotros have no difficulty in discerning another person'due south intention (Carroll, 2009, pp. 71–5). In that case, why would things suddenly stand up differently when it comes to art interpretation? This is not to say that we succeed on every occasion of interpretation, but that we do so in an amazingly large number of cases. That being said, nosotros should non pass up the appeal to intention solely because of the occasional failure.

Another objection is the publicity paradox (Nathan, 2006). The main thought is this: when someone S conveys something p by a production of an object O for public consumption, there is a 2d-order intention that the audience demand not go across O to reach p; that is, in that location is no need to consult S'south get-go-order intentions to understand O. Therefore, when an artist creates a piece of work for public consumption, there is a 2d-order intention that her first-gild intentions non be consulted, otherwise it would indicate the failure of the artist. Actual intentionalism hence leads to the paradoxical claim that nosotros should and should not consult the artist's intentions.

The actual intentionalist'southward response (Stecker, 2010, pp. 153–4) is this: not all artists have the second-order intention in question. If this premise is imitation, so the publicity argument becomes unsound. Even if it were true, the argument would all the same be invalid, because it confuses the intention that the creative person intends to create something standing lonely with the intention that her first-order intention need not be consulted. The paradox will not concord if this stardom is made.

Lastly, many criticisms are directed at a popular argument among actual intentionalists: the conversation statement (Carroll, 2001; Jannotta, 2014). An analogy between conversation and fine art interpretation is drawn, and actual intentionalists merits that if we accept that art estimation is a form of conversation, we demand to accept bodily intentionalism as the right prescriptive business relationship of interpretation, because the standard goal of an interlocutor in a chat is to grasp what the speaker intends to say. (This is a premise fifty-fifty anti-intentionalists accept, just they apparently decline the further claim that art estimation is conversational. See Beardsley, 1970, ch.1.) This analogy has been severely criticized (Dickie, 2006; Nathan, 2006; Huddleston, 2012). The greatest disanalogy between conversation and art is that the latter is more than like a monologue delivered by the artist rather than an interchange of ideas.

One way to meet the monologue objection is to specify more than clearly the role of the conversational involvement. In fact, the bodily intentionalist claims that the conversational interest should constrain other interests such as the aesthetic interest. In other words, other interests can be reconciled or piece of work with the conversational interest. Take the example of the hermeneutics of suspicion for instance. Hermeneutics of suspicion is a skeptical attitude—often heavily politicized—adopted toward the explicit stance of a piece of work. Interpretations based on the hermeneutics of suspicion have to exist constrained past the creative person'southward not-ironic intention in order for them to count every bit legitimate interpretations. For instance, in attributing racist tendencies to Jules Verne'due south Mysterious Island, in which the black slave Neb is portrayed as docile and superstitious, we demand to suppose that the tendencies are non ironic; otherwise, the suspicious reading becomes inappropriate. In this example, the artistic conversation does not terminate up existence a monologue, for the suspicious hermeneut listens and understands Verne before responding with the suspicious reading, which is constrained by the conversational involvement. A conversational interchange is hence completed.

five. Hypothetical Intentionalism

a. Overview

A compromise betwixt actual intentionalism and anti-intentionalism is hypothetical intentionalism, the core merits of which is that the correct significant of a work is determined by the all-time hypothesis most the artist'south intention fabricated by a selected audience. The aim of interpretation is then to hypothesize what the artist intended when creating the work from the perspective of the qualified audience (Tolhurst, 1979; Levinson, 1996).

Two points telephone call for attention. First, it is hypothesis—non truth—that matters. This means that a hypothesis of the actual intention will never be trumped by cognition of that very intention. Second, the membership of the audience is crucial because it determines the kind of evidence legitimate for the interpreter to apply.

A 1979 proposal (Tolhurst) suggests that the relevant audience be singled out by the artist'south intention, that is, the audience intended to be addressed by the artist. Work-meaning is thus determined by the intended audience'southward best hypothesis about the artist'due south intention. This ways that the interpreter will demand to equip herself with the relevant beliefs and groundwork knowledge of the intended audition in club to make the all-time hypothesis. Put another way, hypothetical intentionalism focuses on the audience's uptake of an utterance addressed to them. This existence so, what the audience relies on in comprehending the utterance will be based on what she knows about the utterer on that item occasion. Following this contextualist line of thinking, the pregnant of Jonathan Swift's A Modest Proposal volition not exist the proposition that the poor in Republic of ireland might ease their economic pressure past selling their children as nutrient to the rich; rather, given the background noesis of Swift'southward intended audience, the best hypothesis almost the author'south intention is that he intended the work to exist a satire that criticizes the heartless attitude toward the poor and Irish policy in general.

Withal, at that place is a serious trouble with the notion of an intended audience. If the intended audition is an extremely pocket-size grouping possessing esoteric knowledge of the creative person, meaning becomes a private matter, for the work can only be properly understood in terms of private information shared between creative person and audition, and this results in something close to Humpty-Dumptyism, which is characteristic of absolute intentionalism.

To cope with this problem, the hypothetical intentionalist replaces the concept of an intended audience with that of an ideal or advisable audience. Such an audience is non necessarily targeted by the artist's intention and is ideal in the sense that its members are familiar with the public facts near the artist and her work. In other words, the platonic audience seeks to anchor the work in its context of creation based on public prove. This avoids the danger of interpreting the work on the basis of private evidence.

The hypothetical intentionalist is aware that in some cases there will be competing interpretations which are equally expert. An aesthetic benchmark is then introduced to adjudicate between these hypotheses. The aesthetic consideration comes every bit a necktie breaker: when nosotros reach two or more epistemically all-time hypotheses, the one that makes the work artistically improve should win.

Another notable distinction introduced by hypothetical intentionalism is that between semantic and categorial intention (Levinson, 1996, pp. 188–9). The kind of intention nosotros have been discussing is semantic: information technology is the intention by which an artist conveys her message in the work. Past dissimilarity, categorial intention is the creative person's intention to categorize her production, either equally a work of art, a certain artform (such as Romantic literature), or a detail genre (such every bit lyric verse). Categorial intention indirectly affects a work'due south semantic content because it determines how the interpreter conceptualizes the piece of work at the fundamental level. For instance, if a text is taken as a grocery list rather than an experimental story, we will interpret it every bit saying nothing across the named grocery items. For this reason, the artist's categorial intention should be treated as amongst the contextual factors relevant to her piece of work'due south identity. This move is ofttimes adopted by theorists endorsing contextualism, such as maximizers or moderate intentionalists.

b. Notable Objections and Replies

Hypothetical intentionalism has received many criticisms and challenges that merit mention. A frequently expressed worry is that it seems odd to stick to a hypothesis when newly found evidence proves it to be false (Carroll, 2001, pp. 208–9). If an artist'south private diary is located and reveals that our best hypothesis about her intention regarding her piece of work is false, why should we cling to that hypothesis if the newly revealed intention meshes well with the work? Hypothetical intentionalism implausibly implies that warranted assertibility constitutes truth.

The hypothetical intentionalist clarifies her position (Levinson, 2006, p. 308) by saying that warranted assertibility does not constitute the truth for the utterer's meaning, just it does plant the truth for utterance pregnant. The platonic audience'due south best hypothesis constitutes utterance meaning even if it is designed to infer the utterer's meaning.

Some other troublesome objection states that hypothetical intentionalism collapses into the value-maximizing theory, for, when making the all-time hypothesis of what the artist intended, the interpreter inevitably attributes to the artist the intention to produce a piece with the highest degree of aesthetic value that the work can sustain (Davies, 2007, pp. 183–84). That is, the epistemic criterion for determining the best hypothesis is inseparable from the aesthetic criterion.

In answer, it is claimed that this objection may stalk from the impression that an artist normally aims for the best; however, this does not imply that she would anticipate and intend the artistically best reading of the work. It follows that it is not necessary that the best reading exist what the creative person most likely intended fifty-fifty if she could have intended it. The objector replies that, however, the state of affairs in which we have 2 epistemically plausible readings while one is junior cannot arise, because we would adopt the inferior reading only when the superior reading is falsified by evidence.

The third objection is that the distinction between public and private bear witness is blurry (Carroll, 2001, p. 212). Is public evidence published bear witness? Does published information from private sources count as public? The answer from the hypothetical intentionalist emphasizes that this is non a distinction between published and unpublished data (Levinson, 2006, p. 310). The relevant public context should be reconstrued every bit what the artist appears to have wanted the audience to know about the circumstances of the work's creation. This means that if it appears that the artist did non desire to brand certain proclamations of intent known to the audience, so this evidence, even if published at a subsequently point, does not constitute the public context to be considered for interpretation.

Finally, two notable counterexamples to hypothetical intentionalism take been proposed (Stecker, 2010, pp. 159–60). The starting time counterexample is that W means p only p is not intended by the artist and the audience is justified in believing that p is not intended. In this instance hypothetical intentionalism falsely implies that Westward does not mean p. For example, it is famously known amidst readers of Sherlock Holmes adventures that Dr. Watson's war wound appears in two different locations. On one occasion the wound is said to be on his arm, while on another it is on his thigh. In other words the Holmes story fictionally asserts impossibility regarding Watson'due south wound. Just given the realistic style of the Holmes adventures, the all-time hypothesis of authorial intent in this case would deny that the impossibility is part of the pregnant of the story, which is patently faux.

Nonetheless, the hypothetical intentionalist would non maintain that Due west ways p, because p is not the best hypothesis. She would not merits that the Holmes story fictionally asserts impossibility regarding Watson's wound, for the best hypothesis made by the ideal reader would be that Watson has the wound somewhere on his trunk—his arm or thigh, only exactly where we do not know. Information technology is a error to presuppose that W means p without following the strictures imposed by hypothetical intentionalism to properly reach p.

The 2nd counterexample to hypothetical intentionalism is the case where the audience is justified in believing that p is intended past the creative person but in fact Westward ways q; the audition would so falsely conclude that W means p. Again, what West ways is determined past the platonic audience's best hypothesis based on convention and context, non past what the work literally asserts. The pregnant of the piece of work is the product of a prudent assessment of the total evidence bachelor.

6. Hypothetical Intentionalism and the Hypothetical Artist

a. Overview

There is a second diverseness of hypothetical intentionalism that is based on the concept of a hypothetical creative person. By and large speaking, information technology maintains that interpretation is grounded on the intention suitably attributed past the interpreter to a hypothetical or imagined artist. This version of hypothetical intentionalism is sometimes called fictionalist intentionalism or postulated authorism. The theoretical apparatus of a hypothetical creative person tin exist traced back to Wayne Booth's account of the "implied author," in which he suggests that the critic should focus on the author we tin can make out from the work instead of on the historical writer, because there is often a gap between the two.

Though proponents of the present brand of intentionalism disagree on the number of acceptable interpretations and on what kind of bear witness is legitimate, they agree that the interpreter ought to concentrate on the appearance of the piece of work. If it appears, based on internal testify (and perhaps contextual data if contextualism is endorsed), that the artist intends the piece of work to mean p, and then p is the right estimation of the work. The creative person in question is not the historical artist; rather, information technology is an artist postulated by the audience to be responsible for the intention made out from, or implied by, the work. For example, if in that location is an anti-war attitude detected in the work, the intention to castigate war should be attributed to the postulated artist, not to the historical creative person. The motivation behind this motility is to maintain work-centered interpretation simply avoid the fallacious reasoning that whatever we find in the work is intended by the real artist.

Inheriting the spirit of hypothetical intentionalism, fictionalist intentionalism aims to make interpretation piece of work-based just author-related at the same fourth dimension. The biggest difference between the two stances is that, as said, fictionalist intentionalism does non appeal to the bodily or real artist, thereby avoiding any criticisms arising from hypothesizing nearly the existent artist such as that the best hypothesis well-nigh the existent artist's intention should be abased when compelling evidence against it is obtained.

b. Notable Objections and Replies

The first concern with fictionalist intentionalism is that amalgam a historical variant of the actual artist sounds suspiciously like hypothesizing well-nigh her (Stecker, 1987). But there is still a difference. "Hypothesizing nigh the bodily creative person," or more than accurately, "hypothesizing the actual artist'southward intention," would be a characterization of hypothetical intentionalism rather than fictionalist intentionalism. The latter does not rail the actual artist's intention but constructs a virtual one. As shown, fictionalist intentionalism, unlike hypothetical intentionalism, is allowed to whatever criticisms resulting from ignoring the actual artist's proclamation of her intention.

A second objection criticizes fictionalist intentionalism for non being able to distinguish between different histories of artistic processes for the same textual appearance (Livingston, 2005, pp. 165–69). For example, suppose a work that appears to be produced with a well-conceived scheme did event from that kind of scheme; suppose farther that a second work that appears the same actually emerged from an uncontrolled process. Then, if we follow the strictures of fictionalist intentionalism, the interpretations we produce for these two works would turn out to be the same, for based on the same appearance the hypothetical artists nosotros construct in both cases would be identical. Simply these two works accept different creative histories and the deviation in question seems likewise crucial to be ignored.

The objection here fails to consider the subtlety of reality-dependent appearances (Walton, 2008, ch. 12). For instance, suppose the exhibit note abreast a painting tells us it was created when the painter got heavily drunkard. Any well-organized characteristic in the work that appears to result from conscientious manipulation by the painter might now either look matted or structured in an eerie fashion depending on the feature's actual presentation. Compare this scenario to some other where a (almost) visually indistinguishable analogue is exhibited in the museum with the showroom note revealing that the painter spent a long menstruum crafting the work. In this second instance the audition'south perception of the work is non very likely to exist the aforementioned as that in the first example. This shows how the credible creative person account can nonetheless discriminate betwixt (appearances of) different creative histories of the aforementioned creative presentation.

Finally, there is frequently the qualm that fictionalist intentionalism ends up postulating phantom entities (hypothetical creators) and phantom deportment (their intendings). The fictional intentionalist can reply that she is giving descriptions only of appearances instead of quantifying over hypothetical artists or their actions.

7. Conclusion

From the above discussion we tin can observe two major trends in the fence. Commencement, most late twentyth century and 21st century participants are committed to the contextualist ontology of art. The relevance of art's historical context, since its first philosophical appearance in Arthur Danto'south 1964 essay "The Artworld," continues to influence analytic theories of fine art interpretation. There is no sign of this trend diminishing. In Noël Carroll's 2016 survey commodity on interpretation, the contextualist basis is still assumed.

Second, actual intentionalism remains the most popular position among all. Many substantial monographs have been written in this century to defend the position (Stecker, 2003; Livingston, 2005; Carroll, 2009; Stock 2017). This intentionalist prevalence probably results from the influence of H. P. Grice's piece of work on the philosophy of language. And again, this trend, similar the contextualist vogue, is still ongoing. And if nosotros see intentionalism as an umbrella term that encompasses not only bodily intentionalism but also hypothetical intentionalism and probably fictionalist intentionalism, the influence of intentionalism and its related emphasis on the concept of an creative person or author will exist fifty-fifty stronger. This presents an interesting dissimilarity with the trend in mail service-structuralism that tends to downplay authorial presence in theories of interpretation, as embodied in the author-is-dead thesis championed by Barthes and Foucoult (Lamarque, 2009, pp. 104–15).

8. References and Further Reading

  • Beardsley, M. C. (1970). The possibility of criticism. Detroit, MI: Wayne State Academy Press.
  • Contains 4 philosophical essays on literary criticism. The kickoff two are among Beardsley'southward most important contributions to the philsoophy of interpretation.

  • Beardsley, Yard. C. (1981a). Aesthetics: Issues in the philosophy of criticism (2nd ed.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
  • A comprehensive book on philosophical problems beyond the arts and likewise a powerful argument of anti-intentionalism.

  • Beardsley, Thou. C. (1981b). Fiction as representation. Synthese, 46, 291–313.
  • Presents the spoken communication act theory of literature.

  • Beardsley, Chiliad. C. (1982). The artful indicate of view: Selected essays. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Academy Press.
  • Contains the essay "Intentions and Interpretations: A Fallacy Revived," in which Beardsley applies his speech act theory to the interpretation of fictional works.

  • Booth, W. C. (1983). The rhetoric of fiction (twond ed.). Chicago, IL: Academy of Chicago Press.
  • Contains the original account of the unsaid author.

  • Carroll, N. (2001). Beyond aesthetics: Philosophical essays. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Contains in item Carroll's conversation statement, discussion on the hermenutics of suspicion, defense of moderate intentionalism, and criticism of hypothetical intentionalism.

  • Carroll, N. (2009). On criticism. New York, NY: Routledge.
  • An engaging book on artistic evaluation and interpretation.

  • Carroll, N., & Gibson, J. (Eds.). (2016). The Routledge companion to philosophy of literature. New York, NY: Routledge.
  • Anthologizes Carroll'south survey commodity on the intention debate.

  • Currie, G. (1990). The nature of fiction. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
  • Contains a defense of fictionalist intentionalism.

  • Currie, Chiliad. (1991). Piece of work and text. Mind, 100, 325–40.
  • Presents how a commitment to contextualism leads to an of import distinction between work and text in the case of literature.

  • Danto, A. C. (1964). The artworld. Journal of Philosophy, 61, 571–84.
  • First newspaper to draw attention to the relevance of a piece of work's context of production.

  • Davies, Southward. (2005). Beardsley and the autonomy of the work of art. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 63, 179–83.
  • Argues that Beardsley is actually a contextualist.

  • Davies, South. (2007). Philosophical perspectives on art. Oxford, England: Oxford University Printing.
  • Role Two contains Davies' defense force of the maximizing position and criticisms of other positions.

  • Dickie, G. (2006). Intentions: Conversations and art. British Journal of Aesthetics, 46, 71–81.
  • Criticizes Carroll's conversation argument and bodily intentionalism.

  • Goldman, A. H. (2013). Philosophy and the novel. Oxford, England: Oxford University Printing.
  • Contains a defense of the value-maximizing theory without a contextualist commitment.

  • Hirsch, E. D. (1967). Validity in estimation. New Haven, CT: Yale Academy Printing.
  • The about representative presentation of extreme intentionalism.

  • Hirsch, E. D. (1976). The aims of interpretation. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • Contains a collection of essays expanding Hirsh'due south views on interpretation.

  • Huddleston, A. (2012). The conversation argument for actual intentionalism. British Journal of Aesthetics, 52, 241–56.
  • A vivid criticism of Carroll's conversation argument.

  • Iseminger, Thou. (Ed.). (1992). Intention & interpretation. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Printing.
  • A valuable collection of essays featuring Beardsley'southward business relationship of the piece of work's autonomy, Knapp and Michaels' absolute intentionalism, Iseminger's extreme intentionalism, Nathan'due south business relationship of the postulated artist, Levinson's hypothetical intentionalism, and eight other contributions.

  • Jannotta, A. (2014). Estimation and conversation: A response to Huddleston. British Journal of Aesthetics, 54, 371–80.
  • A defence of the chat statement.

  • Krausz, M. (Ed.). (2002). Is there a unmarried right estimation? University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
  • Another valuable album on the intention debate, containing in item Carroll's defense of moderate intentionalism, Lamarque'due south criticism of viewing work-meaning as utterance pregnant.

  • Lamarque, P. (2009). The philosophy of literature. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
  • The tertiary and the 4th chapters talk over analytic theories of estimation along with a critical assessment of the writer-is-expressionless merits.

  • Levinson, J. (1996). The pleasure of aesthetics: Philosophical essays. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Academy Printing.
  • The tenth chapter is Levinson'due south revised presentation of hypothetical intentionalism and the distinction between semantic and categorial intention.

  • Levinson, J. (2006). Contemplating fine art: Essays in aesthetics. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
  • Contains Levinson'due south replies to major objections to hypothetical intentionalism.

  • Levinson, J. (2016). Aesthetic pursuits: Essays in philosophy of art. Oxford, England: Oxford Academy Press.
  • Contains Levinson's updated defense of hypothetical intentionalism and criticism of Livingston'southward moderate intentionalism.

  • Livingston, P. (2005). Art and intention: A philosophical study. Oxford, England: Oxford University Printing.
  • A thorough discussion on intention, literary ontology, and the problem of estimation, with emphases on defending the meshing condition and on the criticisms of the two versions of hypothetical intentionalism.

  • Nathan, D. O. (1982). Irony and the artist'southward intentions. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 22, 245–56.
  • Criticizes the notion of an intended audition.

  • Nathan, D. O. (2006). Fine art, pregnant, and artist's pregnant. In K. Kieran (Ed.), Contemporary debates in aesthetics and the philosophy of art (pp. 282–93). Oxford, England: Blackwell.
  • Presents an account of fictionalist intentionalism, a critique of the conversation argument, and a brief recapitulation of the publicity paradox.

  • Nehamas, A. (1981). The postulated author: Critical monism as a regulative ideal. Critical Enquiry, eight, 133–49.
  • Presents another version of fictionalist intentionalism.

  • Stecker, R. (1987). 'Apparent, Implied, and Postulated Authors', Philosophy and Literature eleven, pp 258-71.
  • Criticizes different versions of fictionalist intentionalism

  • Stecker, R. (2003). Interpretation and construction: Fine art, speech, and the police force. Oxford, England: Blackwell.
  • A valuable monograph devoted to the intention fence and its related bug such as the ontology of art, incompatible interpretations and the application of theories of art estimation to police. The book defends moderate intentionalism in particular.

  • Stecker, R. (2010). Aesthetics and the philosophy of art: An introduction. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Contains a chapter that presents the disjunctive conception of moderate intentionalism and the 2 counterexamples to hypothetical intentionalism.

  • Stecker, R., & Davies, S. (2010). The hypothetical intentionalist'south dilemma: A answer to Levinson. British Journal of Aesthetics, l, 307–12.
  • Counterreplies to Levinson's replies to criticisms of hypothetical intentionalism.

  • Stock, K. (2017). Only imagine: Fiction, estimation, and imagination. Oxford, England: Oxford Academy Press.
  • Contains a defense of absolute (the author uses the term "extreme") intentionalism.

  • Tolhurst, W. E. (1979). On what a text is and how it means. British Journal of Aesthetics, xix, 3–14.
  • The founding document of hypothetical intentionalism.

  • Trivedi, S. (2001). An epistemic dilemma for actual intentionalism. British Periodical of Aesthetics, 41, pp. 192–206.
  • Presents an epistemic dilemma for actual intentionalism and defense of hypothetical intentionalism.

  • Walton, K. Fifty. (2008). Marvelous images: On values and the arts. Oxford, England: Oxford University Printing.
  • A collection of essays, including "Categories of Fine art," which might take inspired Levinson'southward conception of categorial intention; and "Style and the Products and Processes of Art," which is a defense of fictionalist intentionalism in terms of the notion "apparent artist."

  • Wimsatt, W. K., & Beardsley, M. C. (1946). The intentional fallacy. The Sewanee Review, 54, 468–88.
  • The get-go thorough presentation of anti-intentionalism, commonly regarded as starting signal of the intention fence.

Author Data

Szu-Yen Lin
Email: lsy17@ulive.pccu.edu.tw
Chinese Civilization University
Taiwan